Summary: Williams’ Critique of Utilitarianism

by
November 21, 2015
Print Friendly, PDF & Email

source

Williams, “A Critique of Utilitarianism”

First, some preliminaries:
It’s important to be clear about what views Williams’ argument, and the other arguments
we’ve been considering, target:

(1) What matters to determining the moral status (right/required, permissible,
impermissible) of my actions?

Consequentialism: Only the amount of good produced by my actions is relevant to their
moral status. The right act is the one that produces the most good. Consequentialism
requires that we can identify what is good before we know what is right.
Deontology?: There may be factors other than the amount of good they produce that are
relevant to determining the moral status of my actions. Some ways of thinking about
this:
(i) there may be constraints on what I may (morally) do for the say of producing the
most good (e.g. sacrificing the innocent, violating rights, …)
(ii) in addition to how much good my actions produce, it may matter whether I am
doing harm to someone to produce it, rather than merely allowing harms to
persist which I could have prevented
(iii)it may matter to the moral assessment of my act whether harms it allows to
happen were brought about by other agents
(iv)some actions may be required or permissible for me in virtue of who I am, even if
they produce less good than alternative actions (agent-relative duties or
permissions)
(v) there may be some other morally-relevant factors, such as whether goods have
been distributed equally, or whether people have gotten what they deserve,
that are not best understood as being themselves goods, as opposed to moral
requirements (if equality, e.g., is to be understood as a good, that might invite
the leveling down objection); and if we do take equal distribution or people
getting what they deserve to be goods, they might not be goods we can
identify without a prior conception of the right – that is, we might think
they’re good because they are right, rather than that promoting them is right
because they are good.

(2) What factors contribute to the goodness of an outcome?

Welfarism: The goodness of outcomes depends only on the amount of individual wellbeing,
counting everyone’s well-being as equally important, they contain.
We might accept Consequentialism but reject Welfarism – e.g., if we think some other
things, such as an equal distribution of well-being or resources, or people’s getting what
they deserve, or some impersonal goods like knowledge or beauty, contribute to the good
beyond the contribution they make to individual people’s well-being.

(3) What factors contribute to a person’s well-being?

Hedonism: The only things that contribute to a person’s well-being are the presence of
pleasure and the absence of pain.
Desire-or-Preference-Satisfaction View: Well-being consists in having your
preferences satisfied.
Objective List View: Being well-off is a matter of having certain goods in one’s life
(such as true friendships, knowledge, the appreciation of beauty, happiness) that are
objectively worth having.
Utilitarianism combines Consequentialism with Welfarism. Mill’s version of
Utilitarianism also adopts a Hedonist account of well-being.
It’s useful to think, as we read, about whether the objections we’re considering are
objections to Hedonism, Welfarism, or Consequentialism.

Williams’ Critique
The examples: George and Jim. Can the Utilitarian/the Consequentialist explain why
George’s and Jim’s decisions seem to us at least difficult? (See Extract in Jim and the Indians)

Three issues:

(1) Consequentialism does not recognize a morally significant difference between
doing something and allowing it to happen. It makes no difference to the moral
status of my action whether I brought about some outcome myself or whether I
merely failed to prevent it.
The Doctrine of Negative Responsibility: “if I know that if I do X, O1 will eventuate, and
if I refrain from doing X, O2 will, and that O2 is worse than O1, then I am responsible for
O2 if I refrain from doing X.” (Is this plausible in the case where O2 is better than O1?)

(2) Consequentialism does not recognise a morally significant difference between
doing something and failing to stop someone else from doing something. That is,
it doesn’t allow that “each of us is specially responsible for what he does, rather
than what other people do.”
Is (2) is importantly different from (1)?
3
(1) asks whether it matters, when we evaluate a person’s actions, whether the harms and
benefits they result in were things the person actively caused, or merely allowed to
happen; (2) asks whether it matters, when we evaluate a person’s actions, whether the
harms and benefits they result in were things the person caused, or whether they were
caused by another agent.
Are we specially responsible for what we do, rather than what we allow to happen? Are
we specially responsible for what we do, rather than what others do, when we could have
prevented them?
We might think that the difference in emphasis between these questions is important. We
might think that the difference between what we do and what we allow isn’t in itself be
morally significant (so that I’m just as responsible for the baby’s death if I don’t pull it
out of the bath when it slips as when I push it under), but that we cannot be held as
accountable for the actions of others that we fail to prevent as for our own actions.
Williams:
“Discussions of [these cases] will have to take seriously the distinction
between my killing someone, and its coming about because of what I do
that someone else kills them: a distinction based, not so much on the
distinction between action and inaction, as on the distinction between my
projects and someone else’s projects.” (p. 363)
But is this right? Does it matter, for example, to the question of whether I ought to send
money for famine relief if that famine was the result of drought or government graft?
Also, might a consequentialist stand by (1) and (2), and explain our differing reactions to,
e.g., Pedro and Jim differently? We might, e.g., think that Jim’s act is as wrong as
Pedro’s but that Jim is less blameworthy, because he acts from less bad motives.

(3) Consequentialism/Utilitarianism threatens to alienate us from the projects that
most define us:
Williams:
“It is absurd to demand of such a man, when the sums come in from the
utility network which the projects of others have in part determined, that
he should just step aside from his own project and decision and
acknowledge the decision which utilitarian calculation requires. It is to
alienate him in a real sense from his actions and the source of his action in
his own convictions. It is to make him into a channel between the input of
everyone’s projects, including his own, and an output of optimific
decision; but this is to neglect the extent to which his actions and his
decisions have to be seen as the actions and decisions which flow from the
projects and attitudes with which he is most closely identified. It is thus,
in the most literal sense, and attack on his integrity.” (p. 363)
What do you think of this? Might we not sometimes be required, by morality, to sacrifice
projects that are extremely important to us? And is it reasonable to have a powerful
objection to killing people that is not based on a powerful objection to their being killed?
Questions:
Are the cases of Jim and George different in important ways? Are our intuitions about
them different?

Can the utilitarian explain some of our uncertainty about how Jim and George should act
from within the utilitarian framework (e.g. by considering long-term effects, or the
effects on George and Jim)? What about a different kind of consequentialist? Relatedly,
should a utilitarian take into account the value or disvalue of feelings which are from the
utilitarian perspective irrational, or which result from irrational (value) judgments? (It
seems to me certainly not!) Also, does the “precedence effect” have weight only if we
assume that others will follow our lead even when doing so is not justified by the
utilitarian calculous?

0 Comments

Leave a Reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.