Handout: Free will and Determinism

October 4, 2008
Print Friendly, PDF & Email

Free Will and Determinism

Issues surrounding free will and determinism often seem like spaghetti: they twist and turn in the mind until you get in a terrible tangle. You are strongly advised, in order to find a clear way through a complex area, to buy my book Free Will and Determinism which gives a much more in depth analysis of these issues from the standpoint of three ideas: freedom, causation and the will. They have very diffferent meanings depending on whether you’re a libertarian, compatibilist or hard detrminist and therein lies the secret of untangling the spaghetti. PB

Introduction

In 1924, an American lawyer called Clarence Darrow took on the case of Leopold and Loeb, the teenage sons of two wealthy Chicago families, who were accused of kidnapping and killing Bobby Franks, a 14-year-old boy, to see what it would be like to commit the ultimate crime. Darrow convinced them to plead guilty and then argued for his clients to receive life imprisonment rather than the death penalty.

Darrow argued that his clients weren’t completely responsible for their actions, but were the products of the environment they grew up in, and that they could not be held responsible for basing their desire for murder on the philosophy of Friedrich Willelm Nietszche. Leopold had written to Loeb before the murder:

“A superman . . . is, on account of certain superior qualities inherent in him, exempted from the ordinary laws which govern men. He is not liable for anything he may do.” Leopold (convicted murderer)

Darrow argued that “this terrible crime was inherent in his organism, and it came from some ancestor … Is any blame attached because somebody took Nietzsche’s philosophy seriously and fashioned his life upon it? … It is hardly fair to hang a 19-year-old boy for the philosophy that was taught him at the university.”

In other words, Darrow was arguing that the two boys should not be held responsible for their actions, which were determined by a mixture of their genes and their education. They should plead guilty – they did murder Bobby Franks and the evidence was irrefutable – but should not receive the sentence of death because they were not fully responsible.

In the end, the judge sentenced Leopold and Loeb to life in prison rather than sending them to be executed.

The case raises interesting questions:

  • To what extent are our choices predetermined by our genes or our upbringing?
  • To what extent should criminals be held responsible for their actions?
  • If we had perfect knowledge, would we discover there is no such thing as free will?

For an interesting article from the New York Times 2007 on this debate, click on this link:

http://www.nytimes.com/2007/01/02/science/02free.html?_r=1&en=7d7a5&ex=1325394000&pagewanted=print

The philosopher’s version of Darrow’s defence

The philosopher’s version of the defence attorney’s argument may be called the ‘Causal Chain argument’ (source: Stanford Encylopaedia).

  1. We have free will (of the kind required for moral responsibility) only if we are the ultimate sources (originators, first causes) of our choices.
  2. If determinism is true, then everything we do is ultimately caused by events and circumstances outside our control.
  3. If everything we do is ultimately caused by events and circumstances outside our control, then we are not the ultimate sources (originators, first causes) of our choices.
  4. Therefore, if determinism is true, we are not the ultimate sources of our choices.Therefore, if determinism is true, we don’t have free will (of the kind required for moral responsibility).

Premise (2) follows from the definition of determinism (at least given two widely accepted assumptions: that there is causation in a deterministic universe and that causation is a transitive relation).

Premise (3) is clearly true. So if we want to reject the conclusion, we must reject Premise (1).

Compatibilists have argued against (1) in two different ways. On the positive side, they have argued that we can give a satisfactory account of the (admittedly elusive) notion of self-determination without insisting that self-determination requires us to be the first causes of our choices. On the negative side, compatibilists have challenged (1) by arguing that it is of no help to the incompatibilist: if we accept (1), we are committed to the conclusion that free will and moral responsibility are impossible, regardless of whether determinism is true or false.

The challenge to (1) takes the form of a dilemma: Either determinism is true or it’s not. If determinism is true, then my choices are ultimately caused by events and conditions outside my control, so I am not their first cause and therefore, if we accept (1), I am neither free nor responsible. If determinism is false, then something that happens inside me (something that I call “my choice” or “my decision”) might be the first event in a causal chain leading to a sequence of body movements that I call “my action”. But since this event is not causally determined, whether or not it happens is a matter of chance or luck. Whether or not it happens has nothing to do with me; it is not under my control any more than an involuntary knee jerk is under my control. Therefore, if determinism is false, I am not the first cause or ultimate source of my choices and, if we accept (1), I am neither free nor responsible (Ayer 1954, Wolf 1990).

In order to defend (1) against the so-called “determined or random” dilemma, above, the incompatibilist has to offer a positive account of the puzzling claim that persons are the first causes of their choices. The traditional incompatibilist answer is that this claim must be taken literally, at face value. We — agents, persons, enduring things — are causes with a very special property: we initiate causal chains, but nothing and no one causes us to do this. Like God, we are uncaused causers, or first movers.

For instance, if Joe deliberately throws a rock, which breaks a window, then the window’s breaking (an event) was caused by Joe’s throwing the rock (another event), which was caused by Joe’s choice (another event). But Joe’s choice was not caused by any further event, not even the event of Joe’s thinking it might be fun to throw the rock; it was caused by Joe himself. And since Joe is not an event, he is not the kind of thing which can be caused. (Or so it is argued, by defenders of the conceptual possibility of agent-causation. See Chisolm 1964 and O’Connor 1995 and 2000, and Pereboom 2001.)

Many philosophers think that agent-causation is either incoherent or impossible, due to considerations about causation. What sense does it make to say that a person or other enduring thing, as opposed to a change in a thing, or the state of a thing at a time, is a cause? Others (Broad 1952, Taylor 1960, van Inwagen 2000, Mele 2006) have argued that even if agent-causation is possible, it would not solve the problem of transforming an undetermined event into one which is in our control in the way that our free choices must be.

Recently some incompatibilists have responded to the “determined or random” dilemma in a different way: by appealing to the idea of probabilistic causation (Kane 1996). If our choices are events which have probabilistic causes (e.g., our beliefs, desires, and other reasons for acting), then it no longer seems plausible to say that we have no control over them. We make choices for reasons, and our reasons cause our choices, albeit indeterministically. Kane’s reply may go some way towards avoiding the second (no control) horn of the dilemma. But it doesn’t avoid the first horn. If our reasons cause our choices, then our choices are not the first causes of our actions. And our reasons are presumably caused, either deterministically or probabilistically, so they are not the first causes of our actions either. But then our actions are ultimately caused by earlier events over which we have no control and we are not the ultimate sources or first causes of our actions.

The nature of the debate

Philosophers have divided on the issue of free will into three camps.

Hard determinists argue that since every event has a cause or many causes, it is nonsense to speak of freedom of the will.  We only claim to have free will because we do not know all the causes of our actions.

Soft determinists or compatibilists (because they argue free will and determinism are compatible with one another) argue that we can have free will even if everything is caused. Free will actually requires determinism, otherwise it is mere chance or randomness. We may be wholly determined by genes, background, environment, feelings etc., but we can still operate as if we were free agents.  Some of these causes are internal to the agent, what we understand by the human will.

Libertarians argue that there is no way of proving hard determinism is true.  Our own experience suggests we make free choices.  We also (as Kant pointed out) need to assume freedom in order to make the idea of responsibility meaningful.  Freedom is the triumph of reason over emotions and desires, something that belongs, with morality, to the metaphysical realm (beyond cause and effect).

In the rest of this handout these three views are analysed in a little more depth.

Hard determinism

The hard determinist case (also, like Kant’s, a metaphysical position beyond proof) can be summarised as follows:

  • 1. The material world is made up of matter which is subject to laws of cause and effect.
  • 2. Science can predict reasonably certainly how things behave according to laws of cause and effect.
  • 3. Because nothing is uncaused, it follows that if we knew everything about the human mind and body, then we would discover that everything, all behaviour is caused, and we could in principle discover these causes.
  • 4. So human freedom is an illusion which results from our (at present) less than perfect knowledge.

The assumption here is crucial: that human beings are the same as material things, obeying certain laws such as the law of cause and effect. Christians, for example, would reject this assumption, arguing that we have a God-given soul which includes free will and sense of right and wrong.

But to the hard determinist we are part of a great causal chain which stretches back to our birth.  Hence although it may appear that I am in control of my actions, and have a thing called “free will”, this is in fact an illusion.  We are, to cite an example the philospher John Locke (1632-1704) produced, like sleeping men who wake up in a locked room and decide to stay there.  It is a real and free decision, so we believe, but in reality we have no other choice, whereas a compatibilist argues it’s enough that I am there voluntarily, and a Kantian would argue I can always, at least, get up and rattle the locked door.

If I am a creature of causes which act on me, then it also follows that I cannot be held responsible for my actions, and the sole purpose of punishment is to show our moral disapproval of certain actions, rather than deter the free will of others to do such things.

Behavioural scientists like B.F. Skinner argue that since we are products of social conditioning (our environment) we ought to control our upbringing and environments in order to ensure the condtioning is positive.  Skinner taught positive and negative reinforcement in order that the causal effects of environment and upbrining were as positive as possible.  Skinner didn’t say we don’t feel free, nor did he deny we have wants and desires, but argued that these desires and wants were conditioned.

Psychologists like Freud and biologists like Dawkins argue that desires are a residue of evolution or previous experiences over which we have no control.  Freud argued that desire is the result of strong subconscious and subrational forces.  He believed the human psyche was subject to impulses which stemmed from the relationship between the id, the ego and the superego (or conscience).

For example, during the oedipal period, Freud believed we want to have sex with the same sex parent and kill the parent of the same sex.

Dawkins argues we have developed a selfish gene which drives the instinct to survive.  We are always battling against other species and threats from within our own species caused by random factors or mutations.  However, he argues that we can transcend this selfish gene.  Indeed, co-operation and kindness to others can be part of our survival strategy: it’s actially in our own best survival interest to co-operate.  We have a developed a “lust to be nice”.

In an appendix to his book The Selfish Gene he argues against a morality based on selfishness.

“There is no reason why the influence of the genes cannot be reversed by other influences…in fact genes only determine behaviour in a statistical sense” (Dawkins1976:267).

Just as sunny days statistically tend to follow red skies, but don’t necessarily and inevitably follow, so selfish behaviour tends to follow selfish genes, but is not an inevitable consequence of them.

The power of genes to determine behaviour has also led to the interest in eugenics or gene manipulation that preceded the second World War.

Francis Galton originated eugenics in France in 1870.  He wrote:

“It may seem monstrous that the weak should be crowded out by the strong, but it is still more monstrous that the races best fitted to play their part on the stage of life should be crowded out by the incompetent, the ailing and the desponding….a mistaken instinct of giving support to the weak” (1870:343).

The issues still arise about our moral right to interfere with genes to produce designer babies, cloned sheep and other determined outcomes.

Libertarianism

All libertarians are incompatibilists. For example, libertarian Peter Van Inwagen believes free will is incompatible with determinism.

Van Inwagen uses the metaphor of a fork in a path, like Robert Frost’s “two roads diverging in a yellow wood”. Both paths are genuinely open to you, as long as you could have gone down either path. This is our internal experience of real choice, of “alternate possibilities” with real power to choose.

The Garden of Forking Paths argument (van Inwagen 1993, Fischer 1994, Ekstrom 2000) begins by appealing to the idea that whenever we make a choice we are doing something like what a traveller does when faced with a choice between different roads. The only roads the traveller is able to choose are roads which are a continuation of the road he is already on. By analogy, the only choices we are able to make are choices which are a continuation of the actual past and consistent with the laws of nature.

If determinism is false, then making choices really is like this: one “road” (the past) behind us, two or more different “roads” (future actions consistent with the laws) in front of us. But if determinism is true, then our journey through life is like travelling (in one direction only) on a road which has no branches. There are other roads, leading to other destinations; if we could get to one of these other roads, we could reach a different destination. But we can’t get to any of these other roads from the road we are actually on. So if determinism is true, our actual future is our only possible future; we can never choose or do anything other than what we actually do.

Several crucial assumptions have been smuggled into van Inwagen’s picture: assumptions about time and causation and assumptions about possibility.

  1. That we “move” through time in something like the way that we move down a road.
  2. That our “movement” is necessarily in one direction only, from past to future.
  3. That the past is necessarily “fixed” or beyond our control in some way that the future is not.

These assumptions are all controversial; on some theories of time and causation (the four-dimensionalist or eternalist theory of time, a theory of causation that permits time travel and backwards causation), they are all false (Lewis 1976, Horwich 1987, Sider 2001, Hoefer 2002).

“Determinism (without these additional and controversial assumptions) does not have the consequence that our “journey” through life is like moving down a road; the contrast between determinism and non-determinism is not the contrast between travelling on a branching road and travelling on a road with no branches”. Stanford Encyclopaedia

As an argument for incompatibilism, the appeal to the metaphor of the Garden of Forking Paths metaphor implies we think that our range of possible choices is constrained by two factors: the laws and the past. We can’t change or break the laws; we cannot causally affect the past. (Even if backwards causation is logically possible, it is not within our power.) These beliefs — about the laws and the past — are the basis of the most influential contemporary argument for incompatibilism: the Consequence argument.

Van Inwagen explains that if determinism is true, then any state of affairs together with the laws of nature entails exactly one unique future. This is known as the CONSEQUENCE ARGUMENT.

The compatibilist cannot show that there are multiple futures open to us. He believes the compatibilist is forced to concede to the NO CHOICE PRINCIPLE. We think we have a choice, but in fact we have no choice. The truth of the No Choice Principle, together with the truth of determinism, entails that we lack free will. The mystery of compatibilism lies in conceding this principle contradicts free will.

To be an incompatibilist we must deny the truth of determinism. If we deny determinism, then human choices are undetermined and are random or uncaused: we lack any control, and that is inconsistent with free will. This is the mystery of incompatibilism.

Denying free will means that, in deciding between two options, it is not really in our power to make one or the other come to be. Van Inwagen thinks this is so incredible that it must be false. If I deny I have free will, I give up the struggle I often face when seeing two paths diverging ahead. Van Inwagen maintains that to believe in free will is thus less of a mystery than believing in determinism and denying free will exists.

Compatibilism – Kant, a special case

Kant believed that although we are influenced by our background, genes, and so on, but that we are not wholly determined by them.  We can escape the tyranny of cause and effect, of desires and emotions, argues Kant, by applying reason to our decisions and making real choices, in a sense transcending our determined past.  We are originating causes of our actions due to the activity of the human mind and will.

Even though in the phenomenal realm, the will is subject to the laws of cause and effect, in the noumenal realm, the will is free to follow the dictates of reason.  To Kant these are two ways of assessing the same reality.  As Richard Dean, an American academic, puts it :

“And as for which is really true, that humans are determined or that they’re free, the answer is that truth and falsity are the concern of theoretical reason, and so from that standpoint it is true that we’re determined and false that we’re free. But justification is the concern of practical reason, and from the standpoint of practical reason, the “true” claim that our actions is determined is irrelevant, and we are justified in taking ourselves to be free”.

So Immanuel Kant argued that it is the mind, exercising reason, which makes us free.  If we act from feelings then we are slaves to our passions, but because the human mind possesses the capacity for self-reflection, we can transcend our feelings and other causal determinants.

Notice that Kant saw freedom as something that is very different from randomness, and as something wholly compatible with laws of the universe.  Roger Scruton explains it like this:

“The free agent we see to be distinguished, not by his lack of constraint, but by the peculiar nature of the constraint which governs him.  He is constrained by reason, in its reception to the moral law.” (Scruton, 2002:157)

Kant believed in the autonomy of the will.  “Autonomy” here means “independence”.  The human will is autonomous in the sense that we are capable of acting from reason, and not from other influences like anger or lust.

The good will is one that acts out of duty to the moral law, according to the categorical imperative (see the handout on Kant).

This belief in the autonomy of the will is an assumption in Kantian ethics.  He cannot prove it; it is something he requires in order to argue for moral responsibility and the ability of you and me to choose “the good”.  It is our own rational reflection on the moral law and reasonableness of, for example, the principle of universalisability which generates our motivation to choose to act morally. The only constraint on our freedom in Kantian ethics is our reason.

Kant argued that we should blame, for example, a child abuser even if we find on investigation that the person was themselves abused as a child.

“Now even if one believes the action to be determined by these causes one nonetheless blames the agent….this blame is grounded on the law of reason, which regards reason as a cause that, regardless of all empirical conditions just named, could have and ought to have determined the conduct of the person to be other than it is” (Critique of Pure Reason).

There are strengths in Kant’s form of free will compatibilism:

  • 1. It seems to correspond to our experience (for example, of wrestling with a dilemma)
  • 2. It allows us to attribute praise and blame.
  • 3. It allows us to believe in a God-given soul which explains our freedom and specialness.

Classical compatibilism (soft determinism)

Classical compatibilism (Hobbes, Hume)

Compatibilists argue that human beings are both free and determined by background, genetics, education and the laws of nature.

One famous compatibilist was the scottish philosopher David Hume (1711-76).  Freedom does not mean an absence of causation, argued Hume.  Indeed, if the laws of cause and effect did not apply, we would simply have randomness.  So free will requires determinism.

Hume argued that our will provides an internal cause in the chain of cause and effect, so that freedom is:

“The power of acting or not acting  according to the determinations of the will; that is, if we choose to remain at rest, we may; if we choose to move, we also may” (Hume, Enquiry Concerning Human Understanding, section 8).

Freedom is, according to Hume, the power to act in such a way as to produce a desired effect, and as long as we are not constrained (eg locked up), then we are free.  Notice this is very close to Locke’s example of the man in the locked room who voluntarily stays there, and is unaware that the room is locked.  What Hume is arguing is that the causal determinants of our action make the action predictable, rather than random, and that our internal cause of the free will (itself subject to cause and effect) is sufficient to give us freedom as long as we are not constrained. So the opposite of liberty (freedom) is not necessity (Hume’s word for determinism), but constraint.

So classical compatibilists like Hume and before him Hobbes (compared elsewhere on this site ) are arguing for a weaker view of freedom than a libertarian like Kant. Some philosophers prefer to call this compatibilist idea of freedom voluntariness.  In effect Hume’s argument is this: many causal determinants affect the human will, but as long as we are not constrained by, for example an internal constraint of addiction (the drug addict is hardly “free”), or an external constraint such as being in prison, then we should be held responsible for our actions.  Perhaps things might have been different if circumstances (antecedent causes) had been different.  But they weren’t.

The 20th-century philosopher A. J. Ayer sums up the soft determinist position when he says:

“If I suffered from a compulsion neurosis, so that I got up and walked across the room, whether I wanted to or not, or if I did so because sombody else compelled me, then I should not be acting freely. But if I do it now, I shall be acting freely, just because those conditions do not obtain; and the fact that my action may nevertheless have a cause is, from this point of view, irrelevant. For it is not when my action has any cause at all, but only when it has a special sort of cause, that it is reckoned not to be free.” A.J.Ayer

What sort of “special sorts of cause” (Hume’s or Hobbes’ constraint) may lead you to say your action isn’t free?

1.

2.

3.

Besides, says the soft determinist, the hard determinist, in equating “caused” with “forced” is making a category mistake. The things that make an act unfree are things like having a gun pointed at you, or being attached to ropes, or being hypnotized, or sleepwalking. All of these can be thought of as causes of behaviour.

Further: click here for an excellent discussion of Hume’s compatibilism.

Modern compatibilism (Robert Kane, Peter Vardy)

The argument of the classical compatibilists like Hobbes and Hume is that free will requires determinism, although the freedom we end up with is a fairly minimal sort.  Interestingly, Robert Bowie’s definition of compatibilism is in grave danger of confusing us. “Compatibilism is the belief that it’s possible to maintain both determinism and free will, because while some actions of our nature are determined, our ability to make moral decisions is not”.  This is not what Hobbes and Hume argued, though it is a possible reading of Robert Kane or Peter Vardy.

At a conference in 2009 Peter Vardy put forward the view that “most people are not free – they’re constrained by their background and cultural conditioning.  Freedom may be an achievement that may need great struggle and hardship to achieve.  For a person really to come to understand the forces that act on him or her, to understand the effects of his/her genetic dispositions on their tendencies and inclinations..is hard and difficult and many never achieve it.  These people, then, may not be free at all.  However this is not to say freedom is not possible – but it is to claim that freedom and wisdom are closely linked and the path to freedom is a long and difficult one that may take the whole of a person’s life and may never be fully accomplished”.

Robert Kane argues something similar, that we experience deep freedom only at times of struggle when we feel pulled in two equally possible directions and have to excercise our minds and wills to choose a path of self-determination.  This struggle is something close to what Neo experiences in the film The Matrix when, in scene 8, Morpheus offers him the red or blue pills, promising only the truth.  In choosing the red pill, Neo is choosing a path of conflict which takes him back into the heart of the Matrix computer programme which is enslaving humans in a world of illusion.  he is chosing Vardy’s hard road of wisdom and enlightenment.

“Do you believe in fate Neo?” asks the determinist Morpheus. The libertarian Neo replies “no, I don’t want to give up my belief in freedom”.

So perhaps Robert Kane and Peter Vardy are not compatibilists at all, but need a new ascription of “limited libertarians”, something closer to Bowie’s mistaken definition of compatibilism.

Here is a shport handout on John Locke’s famous analogy of the locked room (full discussion)  locke on free will.pdf

Conclusions

Equating “caused” with “forced” is like equating “fruit” with “apple”; it’s wrong in both cases because the second thing (apple, forced act) is a sub-class of the first (fruit, caused act). An act which is forced is a kind of caused act, just like an apple is a kind of fruit.  But another kind of caused act is an act of volition or free will. So our belief in cause and effect does not mean we cannot have a type of caused act, one caused by free choice.

To argue that all our actions are caused by something does not mean:

  • a. We have to do that action, that it is inevitable and pre-determined.
  • b. We do not have a choice of alternatives.

So Hume’s classic argument, that free will requires determinism in the sense of a chain of causes and effects, may well be valid. Alternatively, as this debate is metaphysical (beyond scientific proof) then we may want to agree with Kant in consigning free will to the noumenal realm, beyond cause and effect, where reason alone operates, and where the structure of our minds requires freedom to make sense of the world.

Exercise 1:  Here is a link to an article attacking determinism.  Write a response to this article.

http://images.google.co.uk/imgres?imgurl=http://nolans.files.wordpress.com/2009/06/fwvd.jpg&imgrefurl=http://nolans.

Exercise 2: Explain Locke’s analogy of the locked room.

locke on free will.pdf

 

 

 

 

0 Comments

Leave a Reply

This site uses Akismet to reduce spam. Learn how your comment data is processed.